(** * Imp: Simple Imperative Programs *) (** In this chapter, we begin a new direction that will continue for the rest of the course. Up to now most of our attention has been focused on various aspects of Coq itself, while from now on we'll mostly be using Coq to formalize other things. (We'll continue to pause from time to time to introduce a few additional aspects of Coq.) Our first case study is a _simple imperative programming language_ called Imp, embodying a tiny core fragment of conventional mainstream languages such as C and Java. Here is a familiar mathematical function written in Imp. Z ::= X;; Y ::= 1;; WHILE not (Z = 0) DO Y ::= Y * Z;; Z ::= Z - 1 END *) (** This chapter looks at how to define the _syntax_ and _semantics_ of Imp; the chapters that follow develop a theory of _program equivalence_ and introduce _Hoare Logic_, a widely used logic for reasoning about imperative programs. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** *** Sflib *) (** A minor technical point: Instead of asking Coq to import our earlier definitions from chapter [Logic], we import a small library called [Sflib.v], containing just a few definitions and theorems from earlier chapters that we'll actually use in the rest of the course. This change should be nearly invisible, since most of what's missing from Sflib has identical definitions in the Coq standard library. The main reason for doing it is to tidy the global Coq environment so that, for example, it is easier to search for relevant theorems. *) Require Export SfLib. (* ####################################################### *) (** * Arithmetic and Boolean Expressions *) (** We'll present Imp in three parts: first a core language of _arithmetic and boolean expressions_, then an extension of these expressions with _variables_, and finally a language of _commands_ including assignment, conditions, sequencing, and loops. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Syntax *) Module AExp. (** These two definitions specify the _abstract syntax_ of arithmetic and boolean expressions. *) Inductive aexp : Type := | ANum : nat -> aexp | APlus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMinus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMult : aexp -> aexp -> aexp. Inductive bexp : Type := | BTrue : bexp | BFalse : bexp | BEq : aexp -> aexp -> bexp | BLe : aexp -> aexp -> bexp | BNot : bexp -> bexp | BAnd : bexp -> bexp -> bexp. (** In this chapter, we'll elide the translation from the concrete syntax that a programmer would actually write to these abstract syntax trees -- the process that, for example, would translate the string ["1+2*3"] to the AST [APlus (ANum 1) (AMult (ANum 2) (ANum 3))]. The optional chapter [ImpParser] develops a simple implementation of a lexical analyzer and parser that can perform this translation. You do _not_ need to understand that file to understand this one, but if you haven't taken a course where these techniques are covered (e.g., a compilers course) you may want to skim it. *) (** *** *) (** For comparison, here's a conventional BNF (Backus-Naur Form) grammar defining the same abstract syntax: a ::= nat | a + a | a - a | a * a b ::= true | false | a = a | a <= a | not b | b and b *) (** Compared to the Coq version above... - The BNF is more informal -- for example, it gives some suggestions about the surface syntax of expressions (like the fact that the addition operation is written [+] and is an infix symbol) while leaving other aspects of lexical analysis and parsing (like the relative precedence of [+], [-], and [*]) unspecified. Some additional information -- and human intelligence -- would be required to turn this description into a formal definition (when implementing a compiler, for example). The Coq version consistently omits all this information and concentrates on the abstract syntax only. - On the other hand, the BNF version is lighter and easier to read. Its informality makes it flexible, which is a huge advantage in situations like discussions at the blackboard, where conveying general ideas is more important than getting every detail nailed down precisely. Indeed, there are dozens of BNF-like notations and people switch freely among them, usually without bothering to say which form of BNF they're using because there is no need to: a rough-and-ready informal understanding is all that's needed. *) (** It's good to be comfortable with both sorts of notations: informal ones for communicating between humans and formal ones for carrying out implementations and proofs. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Evaluation *) (** _Evaluating_ an arithmetic expression produces a number. *) Fixpoint aeval (a : aexp) : nat := match a with | ANum n => n | APlus a1 a2 => (aeval a1) + (aeval a2) | AMinus a1 a2 => (aeval a1) - (aeval a2) | AMult a1 a2 => (aeval a1) * (aeval a2) end. Example test_aeval1: aeval (APlus (ANum 2) (ANum 2)) = 4. Proof. reflexivity. Qed. (** *** *) (** Similarly, evaluating a boolean expression yields a boolean. *) Fixpoint beval (b : bexp) : bool := match b with | BTrue => true | BFalse => false | BEq a1 a2 => beq_nat (aeval a1) (aeval a2) | BLe a1 a2 => ble_nat (aeval a1) (aeval a2) | BNot b1 => negb (beval b1) | BAnd b1 b2 => andb (beval b1) (beval b2) end. (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Optimization *) (** We haven't defined very much yet, but we can already get some mileage out of the definitions. Suppose we define a function that takes an arithmetic expression and slightly simplifies it, changing every occurrence of [0+e] (i.e., [(APlus (ANum 0) e]) into just [e]. *) Fixpoint optimize_0plus (a:aexp) : aexp := match a with | ANum n => ANum n | APlus (ANum 0) e2 => optimize_0plus e2 | APlus e1 e2 => APlus (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2) | AMinus e1 e2 => AMinus (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2) | AMult e1 e2 => AMult (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2) end. (** To make sure our optimization is doing the right thing we can test it on some examples and see if the output looks OK. *) Example test_optimize_0plus: optimize_0plus (APlus (ANum 2) (APlus (ANum 0) (APlus (ANum 0) (ANum 1)))) = APlus (ANum 2) (ANum 1). Proof. reflexivity. Qed. (** But if we want to be sure the optimization is correct -- i.e., that evaluating an optimized expression gives the same result as the original -- we should prove it. *) Theorem optimize_0plus_sound: forall a, aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a. Proof. intros a. induction a. Case "ANum". reflexivity. Case "APlus". destruct a1. SCase "a1 = ANum n". destruct n. SSCase "n = 0". simpl. apply IHa2. SSCase "n <> 0". simpl. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. SCase "a1 = APlus a1_1 a1_2". simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. SCase "a1 = AMinus a1_1 a1_2". simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. SCase "a1 = AMult a1_1 a1_2". simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. Case "AMinus". simpl. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. Case "AMult". simpl. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. Qed. (* ####################################################### *) (** * Coq Automation *) (** The repetition in this last proof is starting to be a little annoying. If either the language of arithmetic expressions or the optimization being proved sound were significantly more complex, it would begin to be a real problem. So far, we've been doing all our proofs using just a small handful of Coq's tactics and completely ignoring its powerful facilities for constructing parts of proofs automatically. This section introduces some of these facilities, and we will see more over the next several chapters. Getting used to them will take some energy -- Coq's automation is a power tool -- but it will allow us to scale up our efforts to more complex definitions and more interesting properties without becoming overwhelmed by boring, repetitive, low-level details. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Tacticals *) (** _Tacticals_ is Coq's term for tactics that take other tactics as arguments -- "higher-order tactics," if you will. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** *** The [repeat] Tactical *) (** The [repeat] tactical takes another tactic and keeps applying this tactic until the tactic fails. Here is an example showing that [100] is even using repeat. *) Theorem ev100 : ev 100. Proof. repeat (apply ev_SS). (* applies ev_SS 50 times, until [apply ev_SS] fails *) apply ev_0. Qed. (* Print ev100. *) (** The [repeat T] tactic never fails; if the tactic [T] doesn't apply to the original goal, then repeat still succeeds without changing the original goal (it repeats zero times). *) Theorem ev100' : ev 100. Proof. repeat (apply ev_0). (* doesn't fail, applies ev_0 zero times *) repeat (apply ev_SS). apply ev_0. (* we can continue the proof *) Qed. (** The [repeat T] tactic does not have any bound on the number of times it applies [T]. If [T] is a tactic that always succeeds then repeat [T] will loop forever (e.g. [repeat simpl] loops forever since [simpl] always succeeds). While Coq's term language is guaranteed to terminate, Coq's tactic language is not! *) (* ####################################################### *) (** *** The [try] Tactical *) (** If [T] is a tactic, then [try T] is a tactic that is just like [T] except that, if [T] fails, [try T] _successfully_ does nothing at all (instead of failing). *) Theorem silly1 : forall ae, aeval ae = aeval ae. Proof. try reflexivity. (* this just does [reflexivity] *) Qed. Theorem silly2 : forall (P : Prop), P -> P. Proof. intros P HP. try reflexivity. (* just [reflexivity] would have failed *) apply HP. (* we can still finish the proof in some other way *) Qed. (** Using [try] in a completely manual proof is a bit silly, but we'll see below that [try] is very useful for doing automated proofs in conjunction with the [;] tactical. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** *** The [;] Tactical (Simple Form) *) (** In its most commonly used form, the [;] tactical takes two tactics as argument: [T;T'] first performs the tactic [T] and then performs the tactic [T'] on _each subgoal_ generated by [T]. *) (** For example, consider the following trivial lemma: *) Lemma foo : forall n, ble_nat 0 n = true. Proof. intros. destruct n. (* Leaves two subgoals, which are discharged identically... *) Case "n=0". simpl. reflexivity. Case "n=Sn'". simpl. reflexivity. Qed. (** We can simplify this proof using the [;] tactical: *) Lemma foo' : forall n, ble_nat 0 n = true. Proof. intros. destruct n; (* [destruct] the current goal *) simpl; (* then [simpl] each resulting subgoal *) reflexivity. (* and do [reflexivity] on each resulting subgoal *) Qed. (** Using [try] and [;] together, we can get rid of the repetition in the proof that was bothering us a little while ago. *) Theorem optimize_0plus_sound': forall a, aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a. Proof. intros a. induction a; (* Most cases follow directly by the IH *) try (simpl; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity). (* The remaining cases -- ANum and APlus -- are different *) Case "ANum". reflexivity. Case "APlus". destruct a1; (* Again, most cases follow directly by the IH *) try (simpl; simpl in IHa1; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity). (* The interesting case, on which the [try...] does nothing, is when [e1 = ANum n]. In this case, we have to destruct [n] (to see whether the optimization applies) and rewrite with the induction hypothesis. *) SCase "a1 = ANum n". destruct n; simpl; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity. Qed. (** Coq experts often use this "[...; try... ]" idiom after a tactic like [induction] to take care of many similar cases all at once. Naturally, this practice has an analog in informal proofs. Here is an informal proof of this theorem that matches the structure of the formal one: _Theorem_: For all arithmetic expressions [a], aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a. _Proof_: By induction on [a]. The [AMinus] and [AMult] cases follow directly from the IH. The remaining cases are as follows: - Suppose [a = ANum n] for some [n]. We must show aeval (optimize_0plus (ANum n)) = aeval (ANum n). This is immediate from the definition of [optimize_0plus]. - Suppose [a = APlus a1 a2] for some [a1] and [a2]. We must show aeval (optimize_0plus (APlus a1 a2)) = aeval (APlus a1 a2). Consider the possible forms of [a1]. For most of them, [optimize_0plus] simply calls itself recursively for the subexpressions and rebuilds a new expression of the same form as [a1]; in these cases, the result follows directly from the IH. The interesting case is when [a1 = ANum n] for some [n]. If [n = ANum 0], then optimize_0plus (APlus a1 a2) = optimize_0plus a2 and the IH for [a2] is exactly what we need. On the other hand, if [n = S n'] for some [n'], then again [optimize_0plus] simply calls itself recursively, and the result follows from the IH. [] *) (** This proof can still be improved: the first case (for [a = ANum n]) is very trivial -- even more trivial than the cases that we said simply followed from the IH -- yet we have chosen to write it out in full. It would be better and clearer to drop it and just say, at the top, "Most cases are either immediate or direct from the IH. The only interesting case is the one for [APlus]..." We can make the same improvement in our formal proof too. Here's how it looks: *) Theorem optimize_0plus_sound'': forall a, aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a. Proof. intros a. induction a; (* Most cases follow directly by the IH *) try (simpl; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity); (* ... or are immediate by definition *) try reflexivity. (* The interesting case is when a = APlus a1 a2. *) Case "APlus". destruct a1; try (simpl; simpl in IHa1; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity). SCase "a1 = ANum n". destruct n; simpl; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity. Qed. (* ####################################################### *) (** *** The [;] Tactical (General Form) *) (** The [;] tactical has a more general than the simple [T;T'] we've seen above, which is sometimes also useful. If [T], [T1], ..., [Tn] are tactics, then T; [T1 | T2 | ... | Tn] is a tactic that first performs [T] and then performs [T1] on the first subgoal generated by [T], performs [T2] on the second subgoal, etc. So [T;T'] is just special notation for the case when all of the [Ti]'s are the same tactic; i.e. [T;T'] is just a shorthand for: T; [T' | T' | ... | T'] *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Defining New Tactic Notations *) (** Coq also provides several ways of "programming" tactic scripts. - The [Tactic Notation] idiom illustrated below gives a handy way to define "shorthand tactics" that bundle several tactics into a single command. - For more sophisticated programming, Coq offers a small built-in programming language called [Ltac] with primitives that can examine and modify the proof state. The details are a bit too complicated to get into here (and it is generally agreed that [Ltac] is not the most beautiful part of Coq's design!), but they can be found in the reference manual, and there are many examples of [Ltac] definitions in the Coq standard library that you can use as examples. - There is also an OCaml API, which can be used to build tactics that access Coq's internal structures at a lower level, but this is seldom worth the trouble for ordinary Coq users. The [Tactic Notation] mechanism is the easiest to come to grips with, and it offers plenty of power for many purposes. Here's an example. *) Tactic Notation "simpl_and_try" tactic(c) := simpl; try c. (** This defines a new tactical called [simpl_and_try] which takes one tactic [c] as an argument, and is defined to be equivalent to the tactic [simpl; try c]. For example, writing "[simpl_and_try reflexivity.]" in a proof would be the same as writing "[simpl; try reflexivity.]" *) (** The next subsection gives a more sophisticated use of this feature... *) (* ####################################################### *) (** *** Bulletproofing Case Analyses *) (** Being able to deal with most of the cases of an [induction] or [destruct] all at the same time is very convenient, but it can also be a little confusing. One problem that often comes up is that _maintaining_ proofs written in this style can be difficult. For example, suppose that, later, we extended the definition of [aexp] with another constructor that also required a special argument. The above proof might break because Coq generated the subgoals for this constructor before the one for [APlus], so that, at the point when we start working on the [APlus] case, Coq is actually expecting the argument for a completely different constructor. What we'd like is to get a sensible error message saying "I was expecting the [AFoo] case at this point, but the proof script is talking about [APlus]." Here's a nice trick (due to Aaron Bohannon) that smoothly achieves this. *) Tactic Notation "aexp_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "ANum" | Case_aux c "APlus" | Case_aux c "AMinus" | Case_aux c "AMult" ]. (** ([Case_aux] implements the common functionality of [Case], [SCase], [SSCase], etc. For example, [Case "foo"] is defined as [Case_aux Case "foo".) *) (** For example, if [a] is a variable of type [aexp], then doing aexp_cases (induction a) Case will perform an induction on [a] (the same as if we had just typed [induction a]) and _also_ add a [Case] tag to each subgoal generated by the [induction], labeling which constructor it comes from. For example, here is yet another proof of [optimize_0plus_sound], using [aexp_cases]: *) Theorem optimize_0plus_sound''': forall a, aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a. Proof. intros a. aexp_cases (induction a) Case; try (simpl; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity); try reflexivity. (* At this point, there is already an ["APlus"] case name in the context. The [Case "APlus"] here in the proof text has the effect of a sanity check: if the "Case" string in the context is anything _other_ than ["APlus"] (for example, because we added a clause to the definition of [aexp] and forgot to change the proof) we'll get a helpful error at this point telling us that this is now the wrong case. *) Case "APlus". aexp_cases (destruct a1) SCase; try (simpl; simpl in IHa1; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity). SCase "ANum". destruct n; simpl; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity. Qed. (** **** Exercise: 3 stars (optimize_0plus_b) *) (** Since the [optimize_0plus] tranformation doesn't change the value of [aexp]s, we should be able to apply it to all the [aexp]s that appear in a [bexp] without changing the [bexp]'s value. Write a function which performs that transformation on [bexp]s, and prove it is sound. Use the tacticals we've just seen to make the proof as elegant as possible. *) Fixpoint optimize_0plus_b (b : bexp) : bexp := (* FILL IN HERE *) admit. Theorem optimize_0plus_b_sound : forall b, beval (optimize_0plus_b b) = beval b. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 4 stars, optional (optimizer) *) (** _Design exercise_: The optimization implemented by our [optimize_0plus] function is only one of many imaginable optimizations on arithmetic and boolean expressions. Write a more sophisticated optimizer and prove it correct. (* FILL IN HERE *) *) (** [] *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** The [omega] Tactic *) (** The [omega] tactic implements a decision procedure for a subset of first-order logic called _Presburger arithmetic_. It is based on the Omega algorithm invented in 1992 by William Pugh. If the goal is a universally quantified formula made out of - numeric constants, addition ([+] and [S]), subtraction ([-] and [pred]), and multiplication by constants (this is what makes it Presburger arithmetic), - equality ([=] and [<>]) and inequality ([<=]), and - the logical connectives [/\], [\/], [~], and [->], then invoking [omega] will either solve the goal or tell you that it is actually false. *) Example silly_presburger_example : forall m n o p, m + n <= n + o /\ o + 3 = p + 3 -> m <= p. Proof. intros. omega. Qed. (** Liebniz wrote, "It is unworthy of excellent men to lose hours like slaves in the labor of calculation which could be relegated to anyone else if machines were used." We recommend using the omega tactic whenever possible. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** A Few More Handy Tactics *) (** Finally, here are some miscellaneous tactics that you may find convenient. - [clear H]: Delete hypothesis [H] from the context. - [subst x]: Find an assumption [x = e] or [e = x] in the context, replace [x] with [e] throughout the context and current goal, and clear the assumption. - [subst]: Substitute away _all_ assumptions of the form [x = e] or [e = x]. - [rename... into...]: Change the name of a hypothesis in the proof context. For example, if the context includes a variable named [x], then [rename x into y] will change all occurrences of [x] to [y]. - [assumption]: Try to find a hypothesis [H] in the context that exactly matches the goal; if one is found, behave just like [apply H]. - [contradiction]: Try to find a hypothesis [H] in the current context that is logically equivalent to [False]. If one is found, solve the goal. - [constructor]: Try to find a constructor [c] (from some [Inductive] definition in the current environment) that can be applied to solve the current goal. If one is found, behave like [apply c]. *) (** We'll see many examples of these in the proofs below. *) (* ####################################################### *) (** * Evaluation as a Relation *) (** We have presented [aeval] and [beval] as functions defined by [Fixpoints]. Another way to think about evaluation -- one that we will see is often more flexible -- is as a _relation_ between expressions and their values. This leads naturally to [Inductive] definitions like the following one for arithmetic expressions... *) Module aevalR_first_try. Inductive aevalR : aexp -> nat -> Prop := | E_ANum : forall (n: nat), aevalR (ANum n) n | E_APlus : forall (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat), aevalR e1 n1 -> aevalR e2 n2 -> aevalR (APlus e1 e2) (n1 + n2) | E_AMinus: forall (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat), aevalR e1 n1 -> aevalR e2 n2 -> aevalR (AMinus e1 e2) (n1 - n2) | E_AMult : forall (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat), aevalR e1 n1 -> aevalR e2 n2 -> aevalR (AMult e1 e2) (n1 * n2). (** As is often the case with relations, we'll find it convenient to define infix notation for [aevalR]. We'll write [e || n] to mean that arithmetic expression [e] evaluates to value [n]. (This notation is one place where the limitation to ASCII symbols becomes a little bothersome. The standard notation for the evaluation relation is a double down-arrow. We'll typeset it like this in the HTML version of the notes and use a double vertical bar as the closest approximation in [.v] files.) *) Notation "e '||' n" := (aevalR e n) : type_scope. End aevalR_first_try. (** In fact, Coq provides a way to use this notation in the definition of [aevalR] itself. This avoids situations where we're working on a proof involving statements in the form [e || n] but we have to refer back to a definition written using the form [aevalR e n]. We do this by first "reserving" the notation, then giving the definition together with a declaration of what the notation means. *) Reserved Notation "e '||' n" (at level 50, left associativity). Inductive aevalR : aexp -> nat -> Prop := | E_ANum : forall (n:nat), (ANum n) || n | E_APlus : forall (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (e1 || n1) -> (e2 || n2) -> (APlus e1 e2) || (n1 + n2) | E_AMinus : forall (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (e1 || n1) -> (e2 || n2) -> (AMinus e1 e2) || (n1 - n2) | E_AMult : forall (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (e1 || n1) -> (e2 || n2) -> (AMult e1 e2) || (n1 * n2) where "e '||' n" := (aevalR e n) : type_scope. Tactic Notation "aevalR_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "E_ANum" | Case_aux c "E_APlus" | Case_aux c "E_AMinus" | Case_aux c "E_AMult" ]. (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Inference Rule Notation *) (** In informal discussions, it is convenient write the rules for [aevalR] and similar relations in the more readable graphical form of _inference rules_, where the premises above the line justify the conclusion below the line (we have already seen them in the Prop chapter). *) (** For example, the constructor [E_APlus]... | E_APlus : forall (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat), aevalR e1 n1 -> aevalR e2 n2 -> aevalR (APlus e1 e2) (n1 + n2) ...would be written like this as an inference rule: e1 || n1 e2 || n2 -------------------- (E_APlus) APlus e1 e2 || n1+n2 *) (** Formally, there is nothing very deep about inference rules: they are just implications. You can read the rule name on the right as the name of the constructor and read each of the linebreaks between the premises above the line and the line itself as [->]. All the variables mentioned in the rule ([e1], [n1], etc.) are implicitly bound by universal quantifiers at the beginning. (Such variables are often called _metavariables_ to distinguish them from the variables of the language we are defining. At the moment, our arithmetic expressions don't include variables, but we'll soon be adding them.) The whole collection of rules is understood as being wrapped in an [Inductive] declaration (informally, this is either elided or else indicated by saying something like "Let [aevalR] be the smallest relation closed under the following rules..."). *) (** For example, [||] is the smallest relation closed under these rules: ----------- (E_ANum) ANum n || n e1 || n1 e2 || n2 -------------------- (E_APlus) APlus e1 e2 || n1+n2 e1 || n1 e2 || n2 --------------------- (E_AMinus) AMinus e1 e2 || n1-n2 e1 || n1 e2 || n2 -------------------- (E_AMult) AMult e1 e2 || n1*n2 *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Equivalence of the Definitions *) (** It is straightforward to prove that the relational and functional definitions of evaluation agree on all possible arithmetic expressions... *) Theorem aeval_iff_aevalR : forall a n, (a || n) <-> aeval a = n. Proof. split. Case "->". intros H. aevalR_cases (induction H) SCase; simpl. SCase "E_ANum". reflexivity. SCase "E_APlus". rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity. SCase "E_AMinus". rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity. SCase "E_AMult". rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity. Case "<-". generalize dependent n. aexp_cases (induction a) SCase; simpl; intros; subst. SCase "ANum". apply E_ANum. SCase "APlus". apply E_APlus. apply IHa1. reflexivity. apply IHa2. reflexivity. SCase "AMinus". apply E_AMinus. apply IHa1. reflexivity. apply IHa2. reflexivity. SCase "AMult". apply E_AMult. apply IHa1. reflexivity. apply IHa2. reflexivity. Qed. (** Note: if you're reading the HTML file, you'll see an empty square box instead of a proof for this theorem. You can click on this box to "unfold" the text to see the proof. Click on the unfolded to text to "fold" it back up to a box. We'll be using this style frequently from now on to help keep the HTML easier to read. The full proofs always appear in the .v files. *) (** We can make the proof quite a bit shorter by making more use of tacticals... *) Theorem aeval_iff_aevalR' : forall a n, (a || n) <-> aeval a = n. Proof. (* WORKED IN CLASS *) split. Case "->". intros H; induction H; subst; reflexivity. Case "<-". generalize dependent n. induction a; simpl; intros; subst; constructor; try apply IHa1; try apply IHa2; reflexivity. Qed. (** **** Exercise: 3 stars (bevalR) *) (** Write a relation [bevalR] in the same style as [aevalR], and prove that it is equivalent to [beval].*) (* Inductive bevalR: (* FILL IN HERE *) *) (** [] *) End AExp. (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Computational vs. Relational Definitions *) (** For the definitions of evaluation for arithmetic and boolean expressions, the choice of whether to use functional or relational definitions is mainly a matter of taste. In general, Coq has somewhat better support for working with relations. On the other hand, in some sense function definitions carry more information, because functions are necessarily deterministic and defined on all arguments; for a relation we have to show these properties explicitly if we need them. Functions also take advantage of Coq's computations mechanism. However, there are circumstances where relational definitions of evaluation are preferable to functional ones. *) Module aevalR_division. (** For example, suppose that we wanted to extend the arithmetic operations by considering also a division operation:*) Inductive aexp : Type := | ANum : nat -> aexp | APlus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMinus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMult : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | ADiv : aexp -> aexp -> aexp. (* <--- new *) (** Extending the definition of [aeval] to handle this new operation would not be straightforward (what should we return as the result of [ADiv (ANum 5) (ANum 0)]?). But extending [aevalR] is straightforward. *) Inductive aevalR : aexp -> nat -> Prop := | E_ANum : forall (n:nat), (ANum n) || n | E_APlus : forall (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (a1 || n1) -> (a2 || n2) -> (APlus a1 a2) || (n1 + n2) | E_AMinus : forall (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (a1 || n1) -> (a2 || n2) -> (AMinus a1 a2) || (n1 - n2) | E_AMult : forall (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (a1 || n1) -> (a2 || n2) -> (AMult a1 a2) || (n1 * n2) | E_ADiv : forall (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 n3: nat), (a1 || n1) -> (a2 || n2) -> (mult n2 n3 = n1) -> (ADiv a1 a2) || n3 where "a '||' n" := (aevalR a n) : type_scope. End aevalR_division. Module aevalR_extended. (** *** Adding nondeterminism *) (* /TERSE *) (** Suppose, instead, that we want to extend the arithmetic operations by a nondeterministic number generator [any]:*) Inductive aexp : Type := | AAny : aexp (* <--- NEW *) | ANum : nat -> aexp | APlus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMinus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMult : aexp -> aexp -> aexp. (** Again, extending [aeval] would be tricky (because evaluation is _not_ a deterministic function from expressions to numbers), but extending [aevalR] is no problem: *) Inductive aevalR : aexp -> nat -> Prop := | E_Any : forall (n:nat), AAny || n (* <--- new *) | E_ANum : forall (n:nat), (ANum n) || n | E_APlus : forall (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (a1 || n1) -> (a2 || n2) -> (APlus a1 a2) || (n1 + n2) | E_AMinus : forall (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (a1 || n1) -> (a2 || n2) -> (AMinus a1 a2) || (n1 - n2) | E_AMult : forall (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat), (a1 || n1) -> (a2 || n2) -> (AMult a1 a2) || (n1 * n2) where "a '||' n" := (aevalR a n) : type_scope. End aevalR_extended. (** * Expressions With Variables *) (** Let's turn our attention back to defining Imp. The next thing we need to do is to enrich our arithmetic and boolean expressions with variables. To keep things simple, we'll assume that all variables are global and that they only hold numbers. *) (* ##################################################### *) (** ** Identifiers *) (** To begin, we'll need to formalize _identifiers_ such as program variables. We could use strings for this -- or, in a real compiler, fancier structures like pointers into a symbol table. But for simplicity let's just use natural numbers as identifiers. *) (** (We hide this section in a module because these definitions are actually in [SfLib], but we want to repeat them here so that we can explain them.) *) Module Id. (** We define a new inductive datatype [Id] so that we won't confuse identifiers and numbers. We use [sumbool] to define a computable equality operator on [Id]. *) Inductive id : Type := Id : nat -> id. Theorem eq_id_dec : forall id1 id2 : id, {id1 = id2} + {id1 <> id2}. Proof. intros id1 id2. destruct id1 as [n1]. destruct id2 as [n2]. destruct (eq_nat_dec n1 n2) as [Heq | Hneq]. Case "n1 = n2". left. rewrite Heq. reflexivity. Case "n1 <> n2". right. intros contra. inversion contra. apply Hneq. apply H0. Defined. (** The following lemmas will be useful for rewriting terms involving [eq_id_dec]. *) Lemma eq_id : forall (T:Type) x (p q:T), (if eq_id_dec x x then p else q) = p. Proof. intros. destruct (eq_id_dec x x). Case "x = x". reflexivity. Case "x <> x (impossible)". apply ex_falso_quodlibet; apply n; reflexivity. Qed. (** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (neq_id) *) Lemma neq_id : forall (T:Type) x y (p q:T), x <> y -> (if eq_id_dec x y then p else q) = q. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) End Id. (* ####################################################### *) (** ** States *) (** A _state_ represents the current values of _all_ the variables at some point in the execution of a program. *) (** For simplicity (to avoid dealing with partial functions), we let the state be defined for _all_ variables, even though any given program is only going to mention a finite number of them. The state captures all of the information stored in memory. For Imp programs, because each variable stores only a natural number, we can represent the state as a mapping from identifiers to [nat]. For more complex programming languages, the state might have more structure. *) Definition state := id -> nat. Definition empty_state : state := fun _ => 0. Definition update (st : state) (x : id) (n : nat) : state := fun x' => if eq_id_dec x x' then n else st x'. (** For proofs involving states, we'll need several simple properties of [update]. *) (** **** Exercise: 1 star (update_eq) *) Theorem update_eq : forall n x st, (update st x n) x = n. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 1 star (update_neq) *) Theorem update_neq : forall x2 x1 n st, x2 <> x1 -> (update st x2 n) x1 = (st x1). Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 1 star (update_example) *) (** Before starting to play with tactics, make sure you understand exactly what the theorem is saying! *) Theorem update_example : forall (n:nat), (update empty_state (Id 2) n) (Id 3) = 0. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 1 star (update_shadow) *) Theorem update_shadow : forall n1 n2 x1 x2 (st : state), (update (update st x2 n1) x2 n2) x1 = (update st x2 n2) x1. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 2 stars (update_same) *) Theorem update_same : forall n1 x1 x2 (st : state), st x1 = n1 -> (update st x1 n1) x2 = st x2. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 3 stars (update_permute) *) Theorem update_permute : forall n1 n2 x1 x2 x3 st, x2 <> x1 -> (update (update st x2 n1) x1 n2) x3 = (update (update st x1 n2) x2 n1) x3. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (* ################################################### *) (** ** Syntax *) (** We can add variables to the arithmetic expressions we had before by simply adding one more constructor: *) Inductive aexp : Type := | ANum : nat -> aexp | AId : id -> aexp (* <----- NEW *) | APlus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMinus : aexp -> aexp -> aexp | AMult : aexp -> aexp -> aexp. Tactic Notation "aexp_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "ANum" | Case_aux c "AId" | Case_aux c "APlus" | Case_aux c "AMinus" | Case_aux c "AMult" ]. (** Defining a few variable names as notational shorthands will make examples easier to read: *) Definition X : id := Id 0. Definition Y : id := Id 1. Definition Z : id := Id 2. (** (This convention for naming program variables ([X], [Y], [Z]) clashes a bit with our earlier use of uppercase letters for types. Since we're not using polymorphism heavily in this part of the course, this overloading should not cause confusion.) *) (** The definition of [bexp]s is the same as before (using the new [aexp]s): *) Inductive bexp : Type := | BTrue : bexp | BFalse : bexp | BEq : aexp -> aexp -> bexp | BLe : aexp -> aexp -> bexp | BNot : bexp -> bexp | BAnd : bexp -> bexp -> bexp. Tactic Notation "bexp_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "BTrue" | Case_aux c "BFalse" | Case_aux c "BEq" | Case_aux c "BLe" | Case_aux c "BNot" | Case_aux c "BAnd" ]. (* ################################################### *) (** ** Evaluation *) (** The arith and boolean evaluators can be extended to handle variables in the obvious way: *) Fixpoint aeval (st : state) (a : aexp) : nat := match a with | ANum n => n | AId x => st x (* <----- NEW *) | APlus a1 a2 => (aeval st a1) + (aeval st a2) | AMinus a1 a2 => (aeval st a1) - (aeval st a2) | AMult a1 a2 => (aeval st a1) * (aeval st a2) end. Fixpoint beval (st : state) (b : bexp) : bool := match b with | BTrue => true | BFalse => false | BEq a1 a2 => beq_nat (aeval st a1) (aeval st a2) | BLe a1 a2 => ble_nat (aeval st a1) (aeval st a2) | BNot b1 => negb (beval st b1) | BAnd b1 b2 => andb (beval st b1) (beval st b2) end. Example aexp1 : aeval (update empty_state X 5) (APlus (ANum 3) (AMult (AId X) (ANum 2))) = 13. Proof. reflexivity. Qed. Example bexp1 : beval (update empty_state X 5) (BAnd BTrue (BNot (BLe (AId X) (ANum 4)))) = true. Proof. reflexivity. Qed. (* ####################################################### *) (** * Commands *) (** Now we are ready define the syntax and behavior of Imp _commands_ (often called _statements_). *) (* ################################################### *) (** ** Syntax *) (** Informally, commands [c] are described by the following BNF grammar: c ::= SKIP | x ::= a | c ;; c | WHILE b DO c END | IFB b THEN c ELSE c FI ]] *) (** For example, here's the factorial function in Imp. Z ::= X;; Y ::= 1;; WHILE not (Z = 0) DO Y ::= Y * Z;; Z ::= Z - 1 END When this command terminates, the variable [Y] will contain the factorial of the initial value of [X]. *) (** Here is the formal definition of the syntax of commands: *) Inductive com : Type := | CSkip : com | CAss : id -> aexp -> com | CSeq : com -> com -> com | CIf : bexp -> com -> com -> com | CWhile : bexp -> com -> com. Tactic Notation "com_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "SKIP" | Case_aux c "::=" | Case_aux c ";;" | Case_aux c "IFB" | Case_aux c "WHILE" ]. (** As usual, we can use a few [Notation] declarations to make things more readable. We need to be a bit careful to avoid conflicts with Coq's built-in notations, so we'll keep this light -- in particular, we won't introduce any notations for [aexps] and [bexps] to avoid confusion with the numerical and boolean operators we've already defined. We use the keyword [IFB] for conditionals instead of [IF], for similar reasons. *) Notation "'SKIP'" := CSkip. Notation "x '::=' a" := (CAss x a) (at level 60). Notation "c1 ;; c2" := (CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity). Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" := (CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity). Notation "'IFB' c1 'THEN' c2 'ELSE' c3 'FI'" := (CIf c1 c2 c3) (at level 80, right associativity). (** For example, here is the factorial function again, written as a formal definition to Coq: *) Definition fact_in_coq : com := Z ::= AId X;; Y ::= ANum 1;; WHILE BNot (BEq (AId Z) (ANum 0)) DO Y ::= AMult (AId Y) (AId Z);; Z ::= AMinus (AId Z) (ANum 1) END. (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Examples *) (** Assignment: *) Definition plus2 : com := X ::= (APlus (AId X) (ANum 2)). Definition XtimesYinZ : com := Z ::= (AMult (AId X) (AId Y)). Definition subtract_slowly_body : com := Z ::= AMinus (AId Z) (ANum 1) ;; X ::= AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1). (** *** Loops *) Definition subtract_slowly : com := WHILE BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0)) DO subtract_slowly_body END. Definition subtract_3_from_5_slowly : com := X ::= ANum 3 ;; Z ::= ANum 5 ;; subtract_slowly. (** *** An infinite loop: *) Definition loop : com := WHILE BTrue DO SKIP END. (* ################################################################ *) (** * Evaluation *) (** Next we need to define what it means to evaluate an Imp command. The fact that [WHILE] loops don't necessarily terminate makes defining an evaluation function tricky... *) (* #################################### *) (** ** Evaluation as a Function (Failed Attempt) *) (** Here's an attempt at defining an evaluation function for commands, omitting the [WHILE] case. *) Fixpoint ceval_fun_no_while (st : state) (c : com) : state := match c with | SKIP => st | x ::= a1 => update st x (aeval st a1) | c1 ;; c2 => let st' := ceval_fun_no_while st c1 in ceval_fun_no_while st' c2 | IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI => if (beval st b) then ceval_fun_no_while st c1 else ceval_fun_no_while st c2 | WHILE b DO c END => st (* bogus *) end. (** In a traditional functional programming language like ML or Haskell we could write the [WHILE] case as follows: << Fixpoint ceval_fun (st : state) (c : com) : state := match c with ... | WHILE b DO c END => if (beval st b1) then ceval_fun st (c1; WHILE b DO c END) else st end. >> Coq doesn't accept such a definition ("Error: Cannot guess decreasing argument of fix") because the function we want to define is not guaranteed to terminate. Indeed, it doesn't always terminate: for example, the full version of the [ceval_fun] function applied to the [loop] program above would never terminate. Since Coq is not just a functional programming language, but also a consistent logic, any potentially non-terminating function needs to be rejected. Here is an (invalid!) Coq program showing what would go wrong if Coq allowed non-terminating recursive functions: << Fixpoint loop_false (n : nat) : False := loop_false n. >> That is, propositions like [False] would become provable (e.g. [loop_false 0] would be a proof of [False]), which would be a disaster for Coq's logical consistency. Thus, because it doesn't terminate on all inputs, the full version of [ceval_fun] cannot be written in Coq -- at least not without additional tricks (see chapter [ImpCEvalFun] if curious). *) (* #################################### *) (** ** Evaluation as a Relation *) (** Here's a better way: we define [ceval] as a _relation_ rather than a _function_ -- i.e., we define it in [Prop] instead of [Type], as we did for [aevalR] above. *) (** This is an important change. Besides freeing us from the awkward workarounds that would be needed to define evaluation as a function, it gives us a lot more flexibility in the definition. For example, if we added concurrency features to the language, we'd want the definition of evaluation to be non-deterministic -- i.e., not only would it not be total, it would not even be a partial function! *) (** We'll use the notation [c / st || st'] for our [ceval] relation: [c / st || st'] means that executing program [c] in a starting state [st] results in an ending state [st']. This can be pronounced "[c] takes state [st] to [st']". *) (** *** Operational Semantics ---------------- (E_Skip) SKIP / st || st aeval st a1 = n -------------------------------- (E_Ass) x := a1 / st || (update st x n) c1 / st || st' c2 / st' || st'' ------------------- (E_Seq) c1;;c2 / st || st'' beval st b1 = true c1 / st || st' ------------------------------------- (E_IfTrue) IF b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI / st || st' beval st b1 = false c2 / st || st' ------------------------------------- (E_IfFalse) IF b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI / st || st' beval st b1 = false ------------------------------ (E_WhileEnd) WHILE b DO c END / st || st beval st b1 = true c / st || st' WHILE b DO c END / st' || st'' --------------------------------- (E_WhileLoop) WHILE b DO c END / st || st'' *) (** Here is the formal definition. (Make sure you understand how it corresponds to the inference rules.) *) Reserved Notation "c1 '/' st '||' st'" (at level 40, st at level 39). Inductive ceval : com -> state -> state -> Prop := | E_Skip : forall st, SKIP / st || st | E_Ass : forall st a1 n x, aeval st a1 = n -> (x ::= a1) / st || (update st x n) | E_Seq : forall c1 c2 st st' st'', c1 / st || st' -> c2 / st' || st'' -> (c1 ;; c2) / st || st'' | E_IfTrue : forall st st' b c1 c2, beval st b = true -> c1 / st || st' -> (IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st || st' | E_IfFalse : forall st st' b c1 c2, beval st b = false -> c2 / st || st' -> (IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st || st' | E_WhileEnd : forall b st c, beval st b = false -> (WHILE b DO c END) / st || st | E_WhileLoop : forall st st' st'' b c, beval st b = true -> c / st || st' -> (WHILE b DO c END) / st' || st'' -> (WHILE b DO c END) / st || st'' where "c1 '/' st '||' st'" := (ceval c1 st st'). Tactic Notation "ceval_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "E_Skip" | Case_aux c "E_Ass" | Case_aux c "E_Seq" | Case_aux c "E_IfTrue" | Case_aux c "E_IfFalse" | Case_aux c "E_WhileEnd" | Case_aux c "E_WhileLoop" ]. (** *** *) (** The cost of defining evaluation as a relation instead of a function is that we now need to construct _proofs_ that some program evaluates to some result state, rather than just letting Coq's computation mechanism do it for us. *) Example ceval_example1: (X ::= ANum 2;; IFB BLe (AId X) (ANum 1) THEN Y ::= ANum 3 ELSE Z ::= ANum 4 FI) / empty_state || (update (update empty_state X 2) Z 4). Proof. (* We must supply the intermediate state *) apply E_Seq with (update empty_state X 2). Case "assignment command". apply E_Ass. reflexivity. Case "if command". apply E_IfFalse. reflexivity. apply E_Ass. reflexivity. Qed. (** **** Exercise: 2 stars (ceval_example2) *) Example ceval_example2: (X ::= ANum 0;; Y ::= ANum 1;; Z ::= ANum 2) / empty_state || (update (update (update empty_state X 0) Y 1) Z 2). Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (pup_to_n) *) (** Write an Imp program that sums the numbers from [1] to [X] (inclusive: [1 + 2 + ... + X]) in the variable [Y]. Prove that this program executes as intended for X = 2 (this latter part is trickier than you might expect). *) Definition pup_to_n : com := (* FILL IN HERE *) admit. Theorem pup_to_2_ceval : pup_to_n / (update empty_state X 2) || update (update (update (update (update (update empty_state X 2) Y 0) Y 2) X 1) Y 3) X 0. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (* ####################################################### *) (** ** Determinism of Evaluation *) (** Changing from a computational to a relational definition of evaluation is a good move because it allows us to escape from the artificial requirement (imposed by Coq's restrictions on [Fixpoint] definitions) that evaluation should be a total function. But it also raises a question: Is the second definition of evaluation actually a partial function? That is, is it possible that, beginning from the same state [st], we could evaluate some command [c] in different ways to reach two different output states [st'] and [st'']? In fact, this cannot happen: [ceval] is a partial function. Here's the proof: *) Theorem ceval_deterministic: forall c st st1 st2, c / st || st1 -> c / st || st2 -> st1 = st2. Proof. intros c st st1 st2 E1 E2. generalize dependent st2. ceval_cases (induction E1) Case; intros st2 E2; inversion E2; subst. Case "E_Skip". reflexivity. Case "E_Ass". reflexivity. Case "E_Seq". assert (st' = st'0) as EQ1. SCase "Proof of assertion". apply IHE1_1; assumption. subst st'0. apply IHE1_2. assumption. Case "E_IfTrue". SCase "b1 evaluates to true". apply IHE1. assumption. SCase "b1 evaluates to false (contradiction)". rewrite H in H5. inversion H5. Case "E_IfFalse". SCase "b1 evaluates to true (contradiction)". rewrite H in H5. inversion H5. SCase "b1 evaluates to false". apply IHE1. assumption. Case "E_WhileEnd". SCase "b1 evaluates to false". reflexivity. SCase "b1 evaluates to true (contradiction)". rewrite H in H2. inversion H2. Case "E_WhileLoop". SCase "b1 evaluates to false (contradiction)". rewrite H in H4. inversion H4. SCase "b1 evaluates to true". assert (st' = st'0) as EQ1. SSCase "Proof of assertion". apply IHE1_1; assumption. subst st'0. apply IHE1_2. assumption. Qed. (* ####################################################### *) (** * Reasoning About Imp Programs *) (** We'll get much deeper into systematic techniques for reasoning about Imp programs in the following chapters, but we can do quite a bit just working with the bare definitions. *) (* This section explores some examples. *) Theorem plus2_spec : forall st n st', st X = n -> plus2 / st || st' -> st' X = n + 2. Proof. intros st n st' HX Heval. (* Inverting Heval essentially forces Coq to expand one step of the ceval computation - in this case revealing that st' must be st extended with the new value of X, since plus2 is an assignment *) inversion Heval. subst. clear Heval. simpl. apply update_eq. Qed. (** **** Exercise: 3 stars (XtimesYinZ_spec) *) (** State and prove a specification of [XtimesYinZ]. *) (* FILL IN HERE *) (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 3 stars (loop_never_stops) *) Theorem loop_never_stops : forall st st', ~(loop / st || st'). Proof. intros st st' contra. unfold loop in contra. remember (WHILE BTrue DO SKIP END) as loopdef eqn:Heqloopdef. (* Proceed by induction on the assumed derivation showing that [loopdef] terminates. Most of the cases are immediately contradictory (and so can be solved in one step with [inversion]). *) (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 3 stars (no_whilesR) *) (** Consider the definition of the [no_whiles] property below: *) Fixpoint no_whiles (c : com) : bool := match c with | SKIP => true | _ ::= _ => true | c1 ;; c2 => andb (no_whiles c1) (no_whiles c2) | IFB _ THEN ct ELSE cf FI => andb (no_whiles ct) (no_whiles cf) | WHILE _ DO _ END => false end. (** This property yields [true] just on programs that have no while loops. Using [Inductive], write a property [no_whilesR] such that [no_whilesR c] is provable exactly when [c] is a program with no while loops. Then prove its equivalence with [no_whiles]. *) Inductive no_whilesR: com -> Prop := (* FILL IN HERE *) . Theorem no_whiles_eqv: forall c, no_whiles c = true <-> no_whilesR c. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 4 stars (no_whiles_terminating) *) (** Imp programs that don't involve while loops always terminate. State and prove a theorem that says this. *) (** (Use either [no_whiles] or [no_whilesR], as you prefer.) *) (* FILL IN HERE *) (** [] *) (* ####################################################### *) (** * Additional Exercises *) (** **** Exercise: 3 stars (stack_compiler) *) (** HP Calculators, programming languages like Forth and Postscript, and abstract machines like the Java Virtual Machine all evaluate arithmetic expressions using a stack. For instance, the expression << (2*3)+(3*(4-2)) >> would be entered as << 2 3 * 3 4 2 - * + >> and evaluated like this: << [] | 2 3 * 3 4 2 - * + [2] | 3 * 3 4 2 - * + [3, 2] | * 3 4 2 - * + [6] | 3 4 2 - * + [3, 6] | 4 2 - * + [4, 3, 6] | 2 - * + [2, 4, 3, 6] | - * + [2, 3, 6] | * + [6, 6] | + [12] | >> The task of this exercise is to write a small compiler that translates [aexp]s into stack machine instructions. The instruction set for our stack language will consist of the following instructions: - [SPush n]: Push the number [n] on the stack. - [SLoad x]: Load the identifier [x] from the store and push it on the stack - [SPlus]: Pop the two top numbers from the stack, add them, and push the result onto the stack. - [SMinus]: Similar, but subtract. - [SMult]: Similar, but multiply. *) Inductive sinstr : Type := | SPush : nat -> sinstr | SLoad : id -> sinstr | SPlus : sinstr | SMinus : sinstr | SMult : sinstr. (** Write a function to evaluate programs in the stack language. It takes as input a state, a stack represented as a list of numbers (top stack item is the head of the list), and a program represented as a list of instructions, and returns the stack after executing the program. Test your function on the examples below. Note that the specification leaves unspecified what to do when encountering an [SPlus], [SMinus], or [SMult] instruction if the stack contains less than two elements. In a sense, it is immaterial what we do, since our compiler will never emit such a malformed program. *) Fixpoint s_execute (st : state) (stack : list nat) (prog : list sinstr) : list nat := (* FILL IN HERE *) admit. Example s_execute1 : s_execute empty_state [] [SPush 5; SPush 3; SPush 1; SMinus] = [2; 5]. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. Example s_execute2 : s_execute (update empty_state X 3) [3;4] [SPush 4; SLoad X; SMult; SPlus] = [15; 4]. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** Next, write a function which compiles an [aexp] into a stack machine program. The effect of running the program should be the same as pushing the value of the expression on the stack. *) Fixpoint s_compile (e : aexp) : list sinstr := (* FILL IN HERE *) admit. (** After you've defined [s_compile], uncomment the following to test that it works. *) (* Example s_compile1 : s_compile (AMinus (AId X) (AMult (ANum 2) (AId Y))) = [SLoad X; SPush 2; SLoad Y; SMult; SMinus]. Proof. reflexivity. Qed. *) (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (stack_compiler_correct) *) (** The task of this exercise is to prove the correctness of the calculator implemented in the previous exercise. Remember that the specification left unspecified what to do when encountering an [SPlus], [SMinus], or [SMult] instruction if the stack contains less than two elements. (In order to make your correctness proof easier you may find it useful to go back and change your implementation!) Prove the following theorem, stating that the [compile] function behaves correctly. You will need to start by stating a more general lemma to get a usable induction hypothesis; the main theorem will then be a simple corollary of this lemma. *) Theorem s_compile_correct : forall (st : state) (e : aexp), s_execute st [] (s_compile e) = [ aeval st e ]. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 5 stars, advanced (break_imp) *) Module BreakImp. (** Imperative languages such as C or Java often have a [break] or similar statement for interrupting the execution of loops. In this exercise we will consider how to add [break] to Imp. First, we need to enrich the language of commands with an additional case. *) Inductive com : Type := | CSkip : com | CBreak : com | CAss : id -> aexp -> com | CSeq : com -> com -> com | CIf : bexp -> com -> com -> com | CWhile : bexp -> com -> com. Tactic Notation "com_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "SKIP" | Case_aux c "BREAK" | Case_aux c "::=" | Case_aux c ";" | Case_aux c "IFB" | Case_aux c "WHILE" ]. Notation "'SKIP'" := CSkip. Notation "'BREAK'" := CBreak. Notation "x '::=' a" := (CAss x a) (at level 60). Notation "c1 ; c2" := (CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity). Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" := (CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity). Notation "'IFB' c1 'THEN' c2 'ELSE' c3 'FI'" := (CIf c1 c2 c3) (at level 80, right associativity). (** Next, we need to define the behavior of [BREAK]. Informally, whenever [BREAK] is executed in a sequence of commands, it stops the execution of that sequence and signals that the innermost enclosing loop (if any) should terminate. If there aren't any enclosing loops, then the whole program simply terminates. The final state should be the same as the one in which the [BREAK] statement was executed. One important point is what to do when there are multiple loops enclosing a given [BREAK]. In those cases, [BREAK] should only terminate the _innermost_ loop where it occurs. Thus, after executing the following piece of code... X ::= 0; Y ::= 1; WHILE 0 <> Y DO WHILE TRUE DO BREAK END; X ::= 1; Y ::= Y - 1 END ... the value of [X] should be [1], and not [0]. One way of expressing this behavior is to add another parameter to the evaluation relation that specifies whether evaluation of a command executes a [BREAK] statement: *) Inductive status : Type := | SContinue : status | SBreak : status. Reserved Notation "c1 '/' st '||' s '/' st'" (at level 40, st, s at level 39). (** Intuitively, [c / st || s / st'] means that, if [c] is started in state [st], then it terminates in state [st'] and either signals that any surrounding loop (or the whole program) should exit immediately ([s = SBreak]) or that execution should continue normally ([s = SContinue]). The definition of the "[c / st || s / st']" relation is very similar to the one we gave above for the regular evaluation relation ([c / st || s / st']) -- we just need to handle the termination signals appropriately: - If the command is [SKIP], then the state doesn't change, and execution of any enclosing loop can continue normally. - If the command is [BREAK], the state stays unchanged, but we signal a [SBreak]. - If the command is an assignment, then we update the binding for that variable in the state accordingly and signal that execution can continue normally. - If the command is of the form [IF b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI], then the state is updated as in the original semantics of Imp, except that we also propagate the signal from the execution of whichever branch was taken. - If the command is a sequence [c1 ; c2], we first execute [c1]. If this yields a [SBreak], we skip the execution of [c2] and propagate the [SBreak] signal to the surrounding context; the resulting state should be the same as the one obtained by executing [c1] alone. Otherwise, we execute [c2] on the state obtained after executing [c1], and propagate the signal that was generated there. - Finally, for a loop of the form [WHILE b DO c END], the semantics is almost the same as before. The only difference is that, when [b] evaluates to true, we execute [c] and check the signal that it raises. If that signal is [SContinue], then the execution proceeds as in the original semantics. Otherwise, we stop the execution of the loop, and the resulting state is the same as the one resulting from the execution of the current iteration. In either case, since [BREAK] only terminates the innermost loop, [WHILE] signals [SContinue]. *) (** Based on the above description, complete the definition of the [ceval] relation. *) Inductive ceval : com -> state -> status -> state -> Prop := | E_Skip : forall st, CSkip / st || SContinue / st (* FILL IN HERE *) where "c1 '/' st '||' s '/' st'" := (ceval c1 st s st'). Tactic Notation "ceval_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) := first; [ Case_aux c "E_Skip" (* FILL IN HERE *) ]. (** Now the following properties of your definition of [ceval]: *) Theorem break_ignore : forall c st st' s, (BREAK; c) / st || s / st' -> st = st'. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. Theorem while_continue : forall b c st st' s, (WHILE b DO c END) / st || s / st' -> s = SContinue. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. Theorem while_stops_on_break : forall b c st st', beval st b = true -> c / st || SBreak / st' -> (WHILE b DO c END) / st || SContinue / st'. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** **** Exercise: 3 stars, advanced, optional (while_break_true) *) Theorem while_break_true : forall b c st st', (WHILE b DO c END) / st || SContinue / st' -> beval st' b = true -> exists st'', c / st'' || SBreak / st'. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. (** **** Exercise: 4 stars, advanced, optional (ceval_deterministic) *) Theorem ceval_deterministic: forall (c:com) st st1 st2 s1 s2, c / st || s1 / st1 -> c / st || s2 / st2 -> st1 = st2 /\ s1 = s2. Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted. End BreakImp. (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (short_circuit) *) (** Most modern programming languages use a "short-circuit" evaluation rule for boolean [and]: to evaluate [BAnd b1 b2], first evaluate [b1]. If it evaluates to [false], then the entire [BAnd] expression evaluates to [false] immediately, without evaluating [b2]. Otherwise, [b2] is evaluated to determine the result of the [BAnd] expression. Write an alternate version of [beval] that performs short-circuit evaluation of [BAnd] in this manner, and prove that it is equivalent to [beval]. *) (* FILL IN HERE *) (** [] *) (** **** Exercise: 4 stars, optional (add_for_loop) *) (** Add C-style [for] loops to the language of commands, update the [ceval] definition to define the semantics of [for] loops, and add cases for [for] loops as needed so that all the proofs in this file are accepted by Coq. A [for] loop should be parameterized by (a) a statement executed initially, (b) a test that is run on each iteration of the loop to determine whether the loop should continue, (c) a statement executed at the end of each loop iteration, and (d) a statement that makes up the body of the loop. (You don't need to worry about making up a concrete Notation for [for] loops, but feel free to play with this too if you like.) *) (* FILL IN HERE *) (** [] *) (* <$Date: 2014-02-22 08:43:41 -0600 (Sat, 22 Feb 2014) $ *)